Myth: There's no such thing as society
only individuals and
families.
Fact: Two or more people in a cooperative relationship form a society by
definition.
Summary
Whenever two or more people enter any sort of cooperative relationship,
the result is by definition a social group. Group survival is much
more effective and efficient than individual survival, but coordinating
group survival results in a need for social policy. The market
is not truly a place where individuals can act freely and without
constraint, because markets are social institutions, and the parameters
of legal behavior on the market are set by social agreement.
Argument
"There's no such thing as society," British Prime
Minister Margaret Thatcher once declared. "There are individual
men and women and there are families."
This remarkable statement serves as a useful litmus test for distinguishing
the moderate right from the far right. If you are a conservative
and agree with Ms. Thatcher, you most likely subscribe to the
far right; if not, you are most likely a moderate. (The reaction
of liberals to this audacious claim was predictable: many were
left wondering how a great and sophisticated nation like Great
Britain could elect anyone to high office without even a rudimentary
understanding of sociology.) But as audacious as the claim may
be, it is a common one among neo-conservatives. They believe that
the concept of society is a myth, and in its place we actually
have a collection of disparate individuals.
Perhaps the first important thing to note is that these are semantic
games. Society is a "collection of individuals,"
even formally defined. It's often amusing to watch the verbal
contortions that conservatives go through trying to avoid this
sense of collectiveness. Instead of a society, they claim, we
have a "group" of individuals, or a "collection"
of individuals, or "many" individuals, or a "whole
bunch of" individuals, or even Margaret Thatcher's solution
to the dilemma: "individuals," plural. Yet the moment
two or more individuals establish any sort of cooperative relationship with each
other, the inevitable result, by definition, is a society.
To say that there is no such thing as society is demonstrably
false. Humans are born in groups, raised in groups, work in groups,
play in groups, defend their interests in groups, and die in groups.
These groups are organized, specialized, interdependent, and greater
than the sum of their parts. In fact, individuals owe their very
existence to group behavior -- namely, the pair-bond, or the union
of mother and father. (This is why Ms. Thatcher had to append
the social group "families" to her statement.)
Human beings almost never live outside groups, and if they do,
it is usually only briefly. True hermitism is extremely rare.
Even such recluse authors and rugged individualists as Ralph Waldo
Emerson (who wrote "nothing can bring you peace but yourself"
in his essay Self-Reliance) depended on the publishing
house and national sales to make him world famous and support
his lifestyle.
The reason why true hermitism is almost never seen is because
group survival is more efficient that individual survival. Imagine
how much poorer you would be if you had to grow your own food,
make your own clothes, build your own house, design your own computers,
write your own software, assemble your own automobile, fix your
own microwave, or treat your own health problems. You would probably
become a death risk at the first serious injury or disease. By
specializing in a job in an interdependent economy, you are far
richer and healthier than you would be otherwise.
The advantage of group survival is the reason why most species
practice social behavior. An excellent example of social creatures
whose very survival is locked into their interdependence is the
bee colony. A bee colony comprises three different types of bees:
queens, drones, and workers, each of whom perform complementary
tasks for survival. No individual bee could survive for long on
its own. They are so interdependent that one could say the entire
colony is the real organism; subdivisions of it do not exist independently.
In a similar manner, there is evidence that human beings are genetically
wired for social behavior. It is natural for humans to become
lonely when separated for long from the group, and to yearn for
the friendship and interaction of others. In fact, French sociologist
Emile Durkheim discovered that suicide is a function of integration
into the social group. The less integrated people are, the more
likely they are to commit suicide. (Since Durkheim's discovery,
other factors leading to suicide have also been identified, but
his theory of social integration remains a central one even today.)
(1)
To see how supremely important socialization is, we need only
consider the case studies of children who have been raised in
complete isolation. Fiction writers have often depicted children
raised outside society, usually by wild animals, who are allegedly
superior to their socialized kin. Examples include the "noble
savage" of Jean-Jacques Rousseau and "Tarzan, lord of
the apes" by Edgar Rice Burroughs. However, real feral children
are the exact opposites of their fictional counterparts. Sociologists
know of several documented cases of children raised in complete
isolation, and all behaved more like wild animals than humans.
(2) They could not speak, reacted to humans with fear and hostility,
walked hunched or on all fours, tore into their food like wild
animals, were apathetic to their surroundings, and were unable
to keep even the lowest standards of personal hygiene. Two, Anna
and Isabelle, were discovered at age six. Anna died four years
later, unable to learn anything more than a few rudimentary phrases.
Isabelle received much more excellent care, and under the training
of experts was able to reach a normal level of development in
two years. A third child, Genie, was found when she was thirteen.
She also improved somewhat under expert care, but did not develop
to the level of her age group as Isabelle did. These cases show
that society plays a decisive role in the lives of individuals.
Methodological individualism
One of the far right's most cherished beliefs is methodological
individualism. This holds that all economic and social phenomena can be traced
back to, and explained by, the actions of individuals. Even when
individuals act on behalf of a group, or as part of a group, they are
acting as individuals. Thus, "group behavior" is a false concept.
As political scientist Jon Elster argues: "A family may, after some
discussion, decide on a way of spending its income, but the decision
is not based on 'its' goals and 'its' beliefs, since there are no
such things." (3) Even if the final budget is a compromise that does
not correspond to the wish of any single family member, then
members have nonetheless agreed to the compromise, since compromising
is somehow more rewarding than not compromising.
The opposite of this is methodological holism, or what political
scientists more commonly call structure. This holds that
groups have traits, behaviors and outcomes that cannot be
understood by reducing them to their individual parts. That is, groups
consist not only of individuals, but also relationships
between individuals. It is not enough to say that "the functions and
traits of my car can be reduced to, and explained by, the
atoms that make it." This overlooks an equally important point --
that these atoms need to be shaped into a car. The fact that
atoms are fundamental units that exhibit certain properties actually
explains very little.
An individualist might then object that human beings are not like atoms, in
that people have the ability to choose and act. Atoms cannot shape
themselves into cars all by themselves, but human individuals have the
ability to join groups and shape their own social structures. And
individualists argue that organizing a group best occurs at the
individual level, not the group level.
The problem with this argument is that organization occurs neither
spontaneously nor at an individual level. Consider a car factory that has
thousands of employees. No single worker possesses the
complete knowledge to build an entire car. Each worker's knowledge and responsibility
are specialized and limited, and can only build part of a car. The only
way a car rolls off the assembly line is through the interdependent
efforts of the entire group. So how does
such complex interaction come into existence in the first place? Well,
not by itself. Suppose a car factory has no central organization, and
workers just began building a car, communicating with no one except the workers
whose parts are immediately connected to their own. It could turn out that the
engine workers thought they were building a Mercedes Benz, while the trunk workers
thought they were building a Yugo. Obviously, there needs to be
central organization.
Nor is it correct to say that all central organization can be traced back to
the individual, namely, the group leader. Even in their primary role
as organizers, corporate heads depend on the group. A company president can only
issue general guidelines to his managers, who must inevitably organize and
direct much of their departments on their own. The larger a company gets,
the less personal and direct control a president has over it. He must
delegate out an increasing share of authority and responsibility, and is
more dependent than ever on others to help him run things, investigate
conditions, inform policy, and make recommendations. Thus, the structure
that evolves takes on a life of its own, and cannot be traced back to any
single person. In democratic
institutions, the lack of individualized leadership becomes even more
obvious, since the leader must largely enact the policies favored by the
group (and not any specific voter within it).
Central organization is vital not only to companies, but to societies as
well. Just as there are no examples of anarchic companies, so, too, are there
no examples of anarchic nations. This is not an accident; all groups require
some degree of central organization to be successful.
And it's not just the mere existence of central organization that is so
important; it's also how it structures society. For example, both
North and South Korea have extensive central governments. Both have individual citizens
who share the same culture, language and genetic stock. But North Korea
is totalitarian; South Korea is democratic. And the result of these
different structures is that one suffers crushing poverty, while the other
enjoys booming prosperity.
Fallacies of composition
The belief that humans are autonomous individuals leads to a logical
error called the "fallacy of composition." This fallacy
holds that aggregate behavior is the same as its individual parts.
This is hardly true. Atoms may have certain distinct
properties, but they rarely appear alone in nature; they almost
always form molecules. And these molecules have their own unique
properties which are completely different from the expected combination
of their individual atoms. One example is the combination of two
gases (hydrogen and oxygen) to form a liquid (water).
The same holds for individuals in society. Most of us would agree
that individuals are highly self-interested. But this inner trait
manifests itself in different outward behaviors, depending on
whether the individual is alone or in a group. If we could observe
a lone individual in nature, we would probably identify his outward
behavior as 100 percent selfish. But place a hundred such individuals
together, and the result will not be the same outwardly selfish
behavior multiplied a hundred times over. Rather, their outward
behavior will become 50 percent selfish and 50 percent giving,
as they produce goods for the market, serve customers, obey their
bosses, donate their time and money to friends and family, and
practise other forms of altruism.
There are numerous other examples of social behavior that cannot
be explained on an individual level. One is economic depressions.
In the United States, where rugged individualism and self-reliance
have always been part of the culture, the Great Depression was
a staggering blow to the self-esteem of individuals who could
no longer feed their families. Many took it as a sign of personal
failure. Today we would surely think these individuals were being
too hard on themselves; after all, the Great Depression was a
world-wide, macroeconomic phenomenon. They could no more blame
themselves for personal failure than victims of the Bubonic Plague
could blame themselves for not being sufficiently healthy.
Economics slumps are, in fact, an excellent example of how individual
efforts to avoid financial problems inadvertently result in group-wide
recessions. Most economists (even conservative ones) accept the
following description of recessions by John Maynard Keynes. During
normal times, there is a circular flow of money in the economy.
My spending becomes part of your earnings, and your spending becomes
part of my earnings. For a wide variety of reasons, however, you
may lose confidence in the economy. You may therefore decide to
spend less and save more in anticipation of the tough times ahead.
This may be a rational strategy for an individual, but
it leads to disastrous and unintended consequences for the group
when everyone does it. That is because your decision to spend
less means that I earn less, which makes things tougher for me.
So I follow the same personal strategy; I hoard my money, but
that only makes things tougher for you. The circular flow of money
falters, and the result is a full-blown recession. Keynes believed
that social policies, not individual efforts, were best for relieving
recessions. He called for central banks to expand the money supply,
which would put more money in the hands of consumers and encourage
spending again. And the proof is in the pudding; this approach
has been a resounding success. In the six decades since World
War II, all nations that have followed Keynes' policies have completely
eliminated the once-common depression from their economies.
The fact that groups can accomplish things much more easily and
efficiently than individuals is well-known. Thus, when the group
is faced with a common problem, it makes much more sense to solve
it collectively than individually. For example, imagine a land
where you were personally responsible for dealing with every threat
or problem that came your way. Threatened by crime? Then you can
spend thousands of dollars protecting your home with various safeguards.
Threatened by air pollution? Then you can buy air-purifiers for
your house. Threatened by water pollution? Then you can distill
or buy your own bottled water. Threatened by pesticides in your
food? Then you can grow your own food. Threatened by disease outbreaks?
Then you can quarantine yourself from the rest of the population
or buy your own vaccinations. But in all these instances, simply
adopting the correct social policy is a far more cost-efficient
method of eliminating these threats. An individualistic society
would produce many absurdisms, like the fact that all the energy
used to run air-purifiers would only pollute the air even more. Or
that people would protect themselves from auto accidents by driving tanks instead of
just installing street signs. Or an entire population would
quarantine itself instead of having the Centers for Disease Control
track down, isolate and eliminate the outbreak at its source.
Many conservatives and libertarians acknowledge as much, claiming
that the free market could offer and perform all these social
services more efficiently than government. Let's ignore, for the
moment, the side-issue of whether or not the free market is more
efficient than government. At the true center of this argument
is an admission that the market is a social institution, one that
provides important social services. Acknowledging this role of
the market is incompatible with claiming that "there is no
such thing as society, there are only individuals and families."
Social institutions are not created by disparate individuals.
They require group agreements. Our so-called "free market"
actually consists of two types of social agreements. The first
is the private corporation, which is filled with workers who agree
to act collectively to create and sell a product. The second is
government, which supports, defends and upholds the free market
in which corporations perform their transactions. Government defends
the free market with police and military force, identifies and
protects various types of property, and ensures fair play on the
free market by prosecuting fraud, insider-trading, price-gouging,
copyright infringement, monopolistic abuse, broken contracts,
false advertising, dishonest disclosure, embezzlement, and a thousand
other ways that people can lie, cheat and steal on the free market.
In other words, the market is only "free" within the
parameters that society agrees to establish. Libertarians and
conservatives who believe that the market allows individuals to
act freely as individuals are therefore in error, because the
market itself is first and foremost a social institution. This
would remain true even if government could somehow privatize all
its services. The only question that remains is: what is the best
form of society?
Margaret Thatcher's statement would only be true if the land were
reduced to complete anarchy, where individuals fought solely for
their own survival in a land of kill-or-be-killed. Frankly, her
statement is not a little brain-dead. One has to wonder: if Ms.
Thatcher doesn't believe in the existence of society, then what on earth
did she think she was Prime Minister of?
Return to Overview
Endnotes:
1. Emile Durkheim, The Elementary Forms of Religious Life,
Joseph W. Swain, trans. (Glencoe, IL.: Free Press, 1954 [original
1912]).
2. R. Brown, Words and Things: An Introduction to Language
(New York: Free Press, 1958), Chapter 5; Lucien Malson, Wolf
Children and the Problems of Human Nature (New York: Monthly
Review Press, 1972); Harlan Lane, The Wild Boy of Aveyron (Cambridge:
Harvard University Press, 1976); Harlan Lane and R. Pillard, The
Wild Boy of Berundi: A Study of an Outcast Child (New York:
Random House, 1978); J.A.L. Singh and Robert Zingg, Wolf Children
and Feral Man, (New York: Harper and Row, 1942).
3. Jon Elster, introduction, Rational Choice, Jon Elster, ed.,
(New York: New York University Press, 1986), p. 3. Elster is a
Marxian, not a member of the far-right, but happens to believe in
methodological individualism all the same.